Theoretical discourse in cinema has nothing to envy from
discourse developed in other cultural fields. One way to assess it is by
examining what has or has not been covered by it. Some extensions and
references to the object of this discourse, namely the history of the cinema,
will be obviously required.
Insofar as we know, among the first to express general views
on the cinema was the poet and writer Ricciotto Canudowho, in 1913, founded the
Club of the Seventh Art Friends in Paris — in the following year he joined the
Garibaldinians. Nevertheless, more than twenty years passed from the time he
was discovered until his theoretical discourse became personalized and
autonomous. This happened after 1918, through the activities of the avant-garde
in France and Proletkult in Russia. It is worth reexamining those events,
although they are well-known.
Now that rethinking is being tested and transformations
occur in basic categories - progress, identity, narration, biomedics etc. - it
would be useful to reexamine some of the related concepts such as
"art", "spectacle", or "accomplishment". Let us
start by recalling the several meanings of the term "cinema" (short
for cinematographe). Initially, and according to its inventors, it described
the "device that recorded, developed and projected motion pictures"
(L. Lumière 1971:35).
Soon after, three more meanings were added:
1. The place where films are shown, also called a
"movie theater".
2. The component processes of film production of a
geographical area or an era: Latin American cinema, Japanese cinema, cinema of
the 1930s.
3. The particular art founded and developed on the
"moving image", which corresponds to painting, the theatre etc.
This inclusiveness of many meanings presents us with
challenges. For example, the phenomenon of cinema in its entirety identifies
with art. This identification, which I shall discuss later, was produced by the
theoretical film discourse produced from 1918 to 1925. Paradoxically enough,
both the French and Russian avant-garde formulated the theoretical discourse of
film as a work of art on the basis of polemic against art. But how did this
come about?
An insertion is needed here. The important point which has
eluded quite a few theorists is that we tend to confuse two significantly
different things:
a. the feeling of possession of the object, which derives
from mimesis, and the object΄s internalization via its image (M. Taussig 1993:
XII); when watching a film, internalization is attained by coordinating the
passive flux of consciousness with the flow of the film, and
b. transcendence in the potential goal of creative art, as
perceived by our culture, based on the reorganization of images and, more
generally, representations.
Let us return to the avant-garde. Moussinac΄s article
"The Birth of the Cinema", dedicated to Louis Delluc in 1924, starts
with the phrases "we live in marvelous times" and "an art is
born in our tumultuous age". Many contradictory elements signifying
rupture coexist in the feverish activity of Dada and the French avant-garde
(Germaine Dulac, Louis Delluc, Francis Picabia, Hans Richter, Fernand Leger etc).
In the Dada Manifesto of 1918, it is proclaimed that "Dada has stopped to
take an aesthetic attitude towards life, and this is attained by decomposing
all slogans about moral values, culture and inwardness" (H. Richter
1983:160). Such an anti-art challenge was expressed in Marcel Duchamp΄s
exhibition of the notorious "Bicycle Wheel", a bottle rack and a
urinal.
On the one hand, we have a strong anti-conformist movement
fighting against academics and intellectuals. According to Jean Epstein, film
director and theorist, "it is wrong to think that cinema is for the elite…
because then it would not be cinema but literature" (René Clair 1970:310).
Furthermore, it is well-known that the elite of the West was negatively
predisposed towards the cinematic spectacle. "What made intellectuals
reject it… was the love of the masses" (L. Moussinac 1967:33). Therefore,
one of the reasons the avant-garde turned to film, was its separation from
conformist culture and the potential to take over a virgin field, free from the
hegemony of the elite.
In this virgin space, the avant-garde tried to impose its
own aesthetic values, combined with carnival elements, exaltation, and
burlesque. According to Robert Desnos (1966:166), the contempt of intellectuals
for the burlesque is characteristic. In texts written in 1928, he writes that
the new art belongs to poetry and dreams, it is in itself dream and sensation,
but gets buried under artistic prejudice. Everybody demands the abolition of
Hollywood-style narration and its replacement with the projection of dreamy
magic. They connect films to musical elation and discover the magic of filmed
images as "a music of pictures" (L. Moussinac 1969:63). They are
evidently influenced by R. Canudo in their views on the juxtaposition of the
static arts, the emphasis on burlesque, the "music of the space" and
accept his proposal that "the new art… must be a kind of Sculpture and
Painting developed in time, just like Music and Poetry " (R. Canudo
1982:96). Remarkably enough, the analogy of the succession of
"optical" and "sound waves" in time is also a matter of
concern for contemporary painters (S. Theodoraki 1984:32).
There are significant similarities between Proletkult and
the avant-garde. Both trends defy bourgeois art and turn to popular spectacle.
Intellectual montage is not a carnival element: "A unanimous outcry
against art rose all over: abolition of the "symbolic" element… [and]
art΄s own existence, and replacement by a specific, true representation of life
without the mediation of myths and depictions", wrote Sergei Eisenstein.
However, there is also a difference. Russian directors moved away from
Proletkult because "the actual problem was not to denounce the bourgeois
ideology, but to discover which techniques could be borrowed from it and how
those techniques could be reversed so that, instead of passive and theoretical,
they would be rendered active…" (B. Eisenschitz 1975:301).
Generally speaking, the Russian avant garde differed from
the French one because it expressed itself mainly through film directors
instead of the visual artists; its starting points were the analysis of montage
(with Lev Kulechov) and realism, instead of the dreamy and marvelous element
proposed by Robert Desnos (1966:104); it focused on the narrative and time-line
of human action, not on the visual music of frames. Thus, the Russians were
able to formulate the aesthetic rules of film narrative composition (angles and
movements of the camera, size and duration of frame succession, connections,
rhythm).
More elaborations on the subject followed (such as the
anti-narrative theory of André Bazin), and enriched the theory of film as far
as aesthetic was concerned. However, none of them yielded an absolute rule
because, as Christian Metz wrote (1971:29, 98-213), film is open; it can be
neither analysed in ideograms, nor defined by codes. Furthermore, every
creative achievement leads to the revision or change of aesthetic rules. Cinema
as art rose from a head-on collision between aesthetic categories and eternity.
The Greek element in film
The postmodernist critique of the Western cultural tradition
does not monopolise the revision of concepts. Theoretical criticism is
generally obliged to examine the conditions under which knowledge is produced,
so as to rescue it from sterility and repetition. The means of theoretical
criticism are: historical approach, transfer to a broad social or
anthropological perspective, holistic examination and analysis of
contradictions.
Let us examine the problems which appeared in Greece. Firstly,
how was theoretical film discourse established in a country where film
production was highly peculiar and only minimally compliant to the western
standards of cinema? And the second interconnected issue is: how
"Greek" was this production and what was its theoretical foundation?
We shall start by examining the second point.
It is well-known that there are several national cinemas.
There are many reasons why cinema is connected to the nation-state. First of
all, cinema is connected with the rise of the middle class and, since it relies
on industrial production, it is in need of a broad market, provided by the
nation-state. At the same time, a film is a cultural product of mass
distribution and therefore needs mass ideological acceptance, which is produced
during the process of development of the cinema. As the film carries shared
collective experiences and behavioural models, it assists in the formation of
collective and consensual identity. Therefore, there has always been mutual
support between film and the nation-state. However, and in opposition to the
theatre, film is not addressed at the elite, but is a spectacle for the people;
this means that the collective identity formed does not always conform to the
official national identity. In certain cases, such as that of the New Greek
Cinema (NGC) of 1965-1975 and the Latin American Cinema, national cinema had a
mostly social character and was inconsistent with the nation-state.
The Modern Greek State raised barriers against Turkish
cultural influence, because its ideology was founded on being hostile to
Turkey; in contrast, the bridge to the influence of the West was left open. For
the elite, western influence came from the countries where they had been
educated: Germany and France. For the rest of society, it came from
neighbouring Italy, which contributed anarchist ideas, music, song, and revue.
Later, the Italian influence also expanded in cinema, with melodramatic
subjects and realistic every-day expression.
Educational institutions and the elite undertook the task to
impose the national identity on the cultural level; the effort to that end was
multi-faceted and included:
1. The de-culturisation of the heterogeneous Greek tradition
and its re-culturisation with the help of folklore.
2. Restriction of influences, as in the resolve of the
conflict between the literary school of Athens, and the literary tradition of
the Ionian Islands and its Italian influences.
3. Reconnection with the ideals of Ancient Greek
civilization; namely, imposition of the official ideology that Modern Greek
civilization was its continuation. The notion of the Ancient Greek model had
arisen in Europe circa 1650, following the dispute between the supporters of
the ancient Greeks (who claimed that Ancient Greece said it all) and
contemporary people; it was established by Winckelmann circa 1750. This
rhetorical ideology used katharevousa, a rhetorical version of the Greek
language. At the end of the 19th century, the notion of the continuity of the
Greek people is expressed as follows: in architecture, with neoclassisicm; in
music, with the National School of Music established by D. Lavrangas and M.
Kalomoiris; in poetry, with the Athenian School; in painting, with Parthenis;
in history, with Paparrigopoulos, and so on.
National ideology is oriented towards the worship of Ancient
Greek civilization, but Greek cinema lacks its basic features of clarity,
austerity in style, and magnificence. Although it bore Italian influences, it
never imitated Italian historical cinema (Pastrone etc). The most outstanding
feature of Greek cinema is the transfer of the revue show onto the screen. The
script-writers and technicians, the sets, the positioning of the camera, the
width of shots and the subjects, all come from the popular revue. On the other
hand, the heroes are evidently influenced by the traditional shadow puppetry of
Karagiozis; but cinema has been called "the art of shadows" anyway.
During the period of internal migration (1948-1973), the
cinema offered the semblance of participation in public life to newcomers in
the cities. It became more popular than the revue or Karagiozis; it was an
expression of the dream to own a flat in the city and it masked submissiveness.
The basic film genres were melodrama, folklore, farce, and musical. As A.
Goldman wrote (1971:73), there is no "unity of structure", since
several film models and breaks coexist in society. The dominant genre was
farce, minimally—if at all—compliant with the sobriety of official ideology.
Following that, one should not be surprised by the state΄s
callousness and the subsequent constant protest of film-makers during the
second half of the 20th century, both through the press (Vion Papamichalis
30-10-52) and professional associations or unions. Despite, or perhaps because
of the fact that the state endorsed the production of nationalistic films (The
Dawn of Victory, 1922 etc.), its policy on film was described as "a
ridiculous model of arbitrariness" (S. Alexandropoulou 6-1-80).
Furthermore, the state imposed strict censorship, thus labeling all Greek film
production "suspect". It is hard to conceal the gap between Greek
film and the nation-state. However, the callousness of the state did not affect
the increase in films made or tickets sold.
With the above, I do not intend to imply that the state is
to be completely rejected, as it is more complex than just a system of power
mechanisms. Apart from those, the state also contains social struggle and its
accomplishments, accumulated human effort, formulation of negotiation sectors,
as well as the existence of contradictions. The point on which I focus is the
contradiction and gap between state and film. Theoretical discourse has
undoubtedly contributed to this juxtaposition. However, the callousness of the
state, the embargo against film-making, the relationships of dependence and the
pressure to modernise have not been adequately analysed; the influence of the
structure of film production, as revealed by the fact that most companies were
established to produce a singular film (V. Papamichalis 30-10-52), was not
studied; the resistance of such structures and their opposition to
modernization was not investigated. The aesthetic element was separated from
its ideological and sociopolitical definitions.
Intellect and theoretical discourse
The other problem mentioned before is the position
theoretical discourse took on films of Greek production.
Theoretical discourse
comes in both verbal and written form. The verbal form includes analysis of
films in clubs and special screenings, courses on cinema, and cinema schooling.
The written form consists of:
1. History books such as the works of A. Moschovakis (1957),
F. Iliadis (1960), N. Mikelidis (1962), G. Soldatos (1979, 1982, 1988-91, 1995,
1999, 2000), A. Mitropoulos (1980), M. Komninos (2000) etc.
2. Books on special issues such as:
a. manuals for
camera operators (G. Kavagias, 1978), film editors (T. Davlopoulos, 1985),
script-writers (A. Kechagias, 1997) etc.
b. critic essays
on the Greek diaspora (Ch. Sotiropoulou, 1995), on the position of women in
cinema (N. Kolovos, 1989), on pioneer movements (S. Theodoraki), on eroticism
(Th. Soumas, 1983), on Theo Angelopoulos (N. Kolovos 1990, E. Stathi 1999) etc.
3. Glossaries and filmographies (V. Rafailidis 1982-83, G.
Dizikirikis 1986, A. Demetriou 1993 etc.).
4. Translations (expanded references in D. Kalantidis,
2000).
Two more categories of written discourse are of special
interest to our subject: theory books and critic essays in newspapers and journals.
Being the upholders of the nation΄s ideology, it was no
surprise that intellectuals faced Greek cinema with indifference or contempt,
or even tried to debase it. One reason was that the nation`s discourse collided
with the cinema`s commercial character; another, that there was a lack of
adequate knowledge on the new art. According to A. Sachinis (22-7-52)—who wrote
that "the cinema is not and will never be art"—Fotos Politis (1934)
is even more negative and considers cinema "a game of the senses, completely
irrelevant to the spirituality and freedom of true… art". Similar remarks
were made by Th. N. Synadinos (23-11-1947), who wrote that cinema "almost
completely swallowed the theatre…[and] rendered speech useless"; V.
Varikas (10-12-1948) held that the cinema "is a business which cares for
anything but art… because art is never judged by its immediate benefits",
and so on. "Who would ever think of asking the cinema to undertake works
that do not belong to it?" wrote Em. Chourmouzios in the press (7-12-1948).
Very few intellectuals, such as V. Rotas (1930), Th. Moustoxydis (1943) and T.
Mouzenidis (21-12-1948), accepted the inclusion of film in the arts.
It is worth to note that the first works of theory on the
art of film analyse its aesthetic but completely disregard Greek productions.
Solon Makris, who, like the Avant Garde, rejects academism, provides a
psychobiological interpretation of film aesthetic; at the same time, he
emphasizes film`s potential of expression and stresses the weaknesses of Greek cinema:
"Greek cinema is not art… [It provokes] easy tears and easy laughter"
(S. Makris 1951:118). In a book of similar content, Fotis Karamitsos (1963:207)
focuses on the effect of montage-découpage in the process of the mental
representation in its entirety, without any reference to Greek films
whatsoever.
Their distancing from the realm of film production is a
characteristic feature of the art elite. Apart from very few exceptions (for
example, the film Nychterini peripeteia [Nighttime adventures], written and
directed by Angelos Terzakis in 1954), intellectuals avoid film production; and
when they enter it, they follow one of the two routes described below:
1. They introduce
Ancient Greek tragedy, which was the national counterweight to popular revue,
as for example inElectra (1962), Young Aphrodites (1963), and Iphigenia (1977),
by M. Cacoyannis and N. Koundouros. In 1952, G. Seferis wrote about "the
important issue… whether the cinema may be used to transmit poetic speech […].
This solution would greatly contribute to the filming of classical Greek
theatre". Behind the modernist expression, there lurks the ideology of
continuity; this is what separates our two Nobel laureate poets, G. Seferis and
O. Elytis, from the poet C. Karyotakis, who did not win a Nobel prize. Perhaps
for the same reason, this approach proved fruitless.
2. Or, they depict
Greece as an exotic destination for tourists, just like foreigners want to see
us: "a country dominated by the bacchanalian element… (where) Greeks never
stop singing and dancing…" (E. Stefani 1997:74). This is evident in the
films Never on Sunday (Jules Dassin, 1960) and Zorba the Greek (M. Cacoyannis,
1965).
The New Greek Cinema (NGC) was formulated in the
mid-Sixties; as mentioned before, it was initially oriented towards social
issues and included elements related to neo-realism. During the Seventies, it
evolved into a cinéma d`auteur; its main features were detachment from revue
and farce, inclusion of psychological rather than social issues, and exploitation
of the expressive means of film, influenced by the aesthetic of André Bazin.
The effort to build a "national cinema" was completely abandoned. At
the same time, the NGC came into total opposition with "commercial"
film-making; NGC directors were not self-taught like "commercial"
directors, but had studied cinema mainly in France. Therefore:
a. the influence of Italian neo-realism was replaced by that
of the French Nouvelle Vague and
b. film directors who are also producers are replaced by
intellectuals of a new generation. These changes had an effect on theoretical
discourse.
Auters and critics
Film criticism started from the time pioneer movements were
fighting for the recognition of cinema as the seventh art. In Greece, the
people who wrote about the cinema immediately after World War II were mostly
theatre critics: M. Ploritis, Em. Chourmouzios, T. Mouzenidis. Film criticism
was "mostly influenced by advertisers΄ jargon" (V. Varikas 10-12-48)
or considered film "a means to entertain the public at large" (A.
Sachinis 15-7-52). Following that period, critics well-versed in film appeared,
such as K. Skalioras, G. Bacoyannopoulos, V. Rafailidis; they wrote mostly
about foreign films, in accordance with the tradition set by G. Makris, film
critic of the newspaper Nea Estia before the war.
After 1975, when NGC had already developed, intellectual
directors were often critics as well. Most of them had similar credentials (MA
in film-making) and culture influences (the Nouvelle Vague aesthetic).
Consequently, several directors also expressed themselves in writing: Th.
Angelopoulos, G. Korras, T. Lykouresis, T. Papagiannidis, N. Lyngouris, Ch.
Vacalopoulos et al. Very few of them were exclusively critics, without ever
having made a film. Up to the end of the 20th century, theorists with special
studies were rare; there were also many self-taught critics. On the other hand,
several people wrote about theoretical issues without being involved in film
criticism (D. Theos, G. Dizikirikis, D. Leventakos, Th. Rentzis, G. Soldatos,
T. Antonopoulos etc) were also film-directors.
It is evident that,
in this period and through the collective contribution of film-directors,
critics, theorists and their associates, there emerged a new intellectual
community, prevalent in the realm of film, which won Greek cinema a central
place as an artistic activity. Critics stood up for NGC films; theoretical
discourse was produced by all members of the community. In other words, if NGC
films failed, this would also mean failure for their critics. And this is how
it went.
We have already mentioned that, after 1975, the film
community consisted of "intellectuals". This new generation elite was
different; instead of the national aesthetic culture, they expressed a
westernized aesthetic view which set them apart from previous film production.
As a result, their perspective on the "old" cinema was based on the
following narrow criteria:
a. Distribution, so as to derogatorily pronounce the old
cinema "commercial".
b. Aesthetic structure, to condemn the old cinema as a
"popular" spectacle.
References on the popularity of the cinema were made in the
press; there was the research of S. Alexandropoulou (6-1-1980) and the negative
position held by V. Rafailidis (3-10-1982), who connected the
"popular" element with "being unfamiliar with complex aesthetic
structures" and "having a narrow education… or no education at
all". Deep down, the discussion about popularity reintroduced the
following dilemma: should culture be homogeneous, or should there be a social
distinction between the elite and the "uninitiated"?
Many denounced the "artistically and commercially
unfortunate Iphigenia" which drained the Greek Film Centre`s budget (S.
Alexandropoulou 6-1-1980), the "non-sensical films" (E. Zachos), and
"the ΄arty΄or ΄personal΄ films which are
praised with ridiculously extensive use of superlatives (as critics
undermine any and all artistic criteria), and then pass into obscurity due to
the indifference or dislike of audiences" (K. Vrettakos 19-10-1980). At
the same time, it is discovered that the "approximately 50% fall in
tickets" is connected to "the cinema of auters" (N. Manolitsis
22-12-1988).
Today, it is accepted that cinema is a popular art (G.
Bacoyannopoulos, N. Kolovos 1-4-2001). Apart from the responsibilites critics
bear for the "rise and fall" of the NGC, the coalition between film,
intellectuals and art is now a thing of the past. The efforts to win back the
audiences by turning to comedy, which was scorned by the NGC, led to an impasse
because popularity was confused with populism. Theoretical discourse is once
more to blame here, for failing to analyze the difference between the two in
its attacks on the latter.
Theorists showed indifference to social and cultural
criteria. They failed to discern the contrast between the popular element and
low budget production on one hand, and the official ideology, the aesthetic
culture, and the theatrical perception of comedy focusing on characters rather
than plot mechanisms on the other. They did not investigate the features of
this para-culture, which deviated from official culture. Namely, they did not
examine whether this para-culture was:
1. an adoption of the popular element, as the latter was
defined by the official culture.
2. a culture of resistance, where farce is combined with
carnival elements.
3. a performance where the tendency to rise socially is
expressed with hypocritically pretending to be "crazy".
4. the reproduction of a climate of submission, where farce
either complements or is the flip side of melodrama.
5. intended to be integrated in industrial production as a
populistic creation.
According to Brecht (1972:44), "the intended purpose of
art is the creation of an islet of non-production". This is why the cinema
is called the alibi of paid labour and the industry of dreams. What was the
part played by foreign influence and the popular—according to the official
culture—element, which seeped through because the manufacturers lacked
specialized education? How can the constant refusal to establish a National
School of Film be explained? What is the difference between low-budget
production and production on an industrial level? Theoretical discourse is obliged
to provide answers to these questions.
Discrepancies in criticism
As has been said before, avant garde movements imposed film
as the seventh art by opposing their contemporary culture and art. This
confirms the view of the aesthetic theorists of our century (W. Deonna, H. Read
etc) that there are no constant rules or laws in art. "Since art… is
trained to open the gate to things being otherwise… art is transgressive… and
iconoclastic", wrote D. Theos (1987:100). But this view undermines the
very essence of criticism. According to lettrism, a new avant-garde current,
"criticism is constantly being disclaimed… the only appropriate foundation
to criticism is to search and project what is new" (M. Lemaitre 1972:44).
David Griffith΄s prediction about video was verified, but his 1924 statement
that "sound films will never come about" proved wrong; Carl Dreyer
(1971:158) was also proved wrong when, in 1955, he upheld that "colour
films cannot be art".
On the whole, film criticism faces a serious problem. If we
accept that there are general aesthetic rules and that a great work of art can
be appreciated by everyone, as some critics argue, "our audience is able
to assimilate the very best food for thought" (E. Chourmouzios 1-4-54) and
"the audiance… is able to discern and appreciate a fine form intuitively.
The proof to that is the unwaning ΄popularity΄ of the works of Aeschylus and Shakespeare…"
(M. Ploritis 24-2-1961). Thus, it is hard to explain the role of criticism.
On the other hand, if we accept that the rules of aesthetic
experience and assimilation are not universal, but the product of a specialized
education which criticism either contains or complements, the following
question arises: how did people comprehend art before the 20th century, when
there was no criticism? Does aesthetic education concern knowledge of special "complex
codes" constituting a "symbolic capital" (P. Bourdieu 1996:12),
so that the initiated may be set apart from the ignorant? If, in comparison
with popular forms of art, fine arts are discerned by aesthetic rules and
education, how does it happen that aesthetic values are acknowledged in certain
previously scorned forms of popular art, such as burlesque, primitivism, or the
Greek naïf artist Theophilos? Therefore, the question is: why criticism?
I have already mentioned the pseudo-dilemma whether culture
should be homogeneous or whether there should be distinction between the elite
and the plebeians. In other words, we must either accept homogeneity of culture
where all share the same criteria, as was the case in now obsolete
unsophisticated "primitive" communities, or accept that culture is
heterogeneous and consists of groups with different values and criteria. In the
first case, criticism is redundant; in the second case, it either tries to
impose its values on other groups or to resist such imposition. Which of the
two does criticism do in our society?
According to one view, criticism mediates between aesthetic
culture and the audience which is "unfamiliar" with it, by analyzing
the second level of symbolism—namely what the director meant; it explains the
way in which the director organised complex codes and suggests which film is a
masterpiece. However, directors are usually unable to explain "what they
meant" and urge the audience to watch the film, not to read the reviews.
Furthermore, several pioneer movements have denounced the concept of
masterpiece.
In order to fulfill the role described above and transmit
culture, criticism should provide:
1. an aesthetic chart of the film; namely, to explain which
genre or school the film belongs to, the model it expresses, the rules it
adopts or rejects etc.
2. a social chart of the film; who it represents and who it
is about, the ideology it expresses, its position in the historical/political
system etc.
3. an analysis of how filmic expressive means are organised
(angles and movement of the camera, size, duration and succession of shots,
connections, montage and rhythm).
It is obvious that most or all of the above are not included
in film criticism, which is mainly restricted to examining the film΄s story and
the performance of the actors, and making hypotheses about deeper symbolisms;
thus, the reader gets the impression that the critic is ignorant of both the
expressive means used in the film and the society the film belongs to, as if
the film΄s criticism were addressed to nobody.
On the other hand, by discovering codes and levels of
symbolism of which the director is not immediately conscious, criticism also
mediates between the director`s creative subconscious and the work. This is
achieved by the use of subjective criteria, which have to be further analysed
meta-critically; alternatively, the critic becomes an auteur on the aesthetic
level, by introducing new aesthetic rules. In the first case, the critic may
become difficult to understand or there may be disagreement between views. I
shall mention some views of critics on Th. Angelopoulos`Megalexandros:
"Megalexandros stands alone… visually abundant and fulfilling… mature in
composition and very advanced—soaring above the general standard of Greek film.
This is the vanguard of the popular element…" (D. Danikas 4-11-1980).
"I shall remind you that it is a poetic political film that flows like a
river… with multiple levels, laden with symbols and historical riddles which
are mostly left unsolved… (it has three) levels of interpretation" (K.
Stamatiou 3-11-1980). "…even the least enthusiastic bow before the
magnificence of the idiosyncratic Megalexandros, a most misunderstood and
gifted failed masterpiece" (O. Andreadakis 10-11-1980). There was
notorious conflict between critics on Laurence Olivier`s Hamlet (E.
Chourmouzios 7-12-1948, G. Skarimbas 11-12-1948), Ingmar Bergman`s The Silence
and so on.
Weakness or consent?
One big and fundamental irony about theoretical filmic
discourse is its inability to liberate itself from the ideology of the
hegemony. Ideology is what we call the explicit (in collective experiences) and
implicit (in rules of behaviour and emotions) prescriptive restrictions which
crystallize into institutional power structures, through the implementation of
power relations, and affect us through socialization, social structures and the
practices which produce and reproduce such experiences and behaviour.
Let us become more specific, without touching on the
complicated matter of art. An artistic film is not cinema itself; it is just a
part of cinema and therefore it is subject to the necessities of cinema.
Neither the art film nor art itself is something far away; they both lie in
culture, which is the system of power structure which we enter in order to act
in accordance to certain cultural standards and experiences. Since this system
is based on power relations, it is contradictory. In the part of art which
concerns us, reaction is expressed through creative or heretic works and by
theoretical discourse. The action system of authority imposes itself through
academic rules, as well as numerous prescriptive mechanisms, which confirm that
the film is not simply art. These mechanisms are:
-the institutional frame (analytically in Ch. Sotiropoulou 1989:48-53).
-censorship, which Jean Mitry (6-11-65) identifies with the
state.
-rituals such as a "national festival, an irreverent
product of vulgar transactions and extortions…" (Th. Rentzis 26-9-1978).
- police raids on cinemas during screenings of I kangeloporta
(22-2-79).
-V. Rafailidis΄ imprisonment because of his article
published in the newspaper Ethnos on 17 October 1983.
-embargo on national cinema.
-"efforts through the direct or indirect pressure of
producers and distribution companies to restrict or silence the views of
critics" (G. Bacoyannopoulos), and so on.
Ironically enough, despite being constantly targeted by the
power system , theorists prefer to follow the road of consent. They disengage
the celestial work of art from mundane institutional limitations. They judge
films according to the rules of their times, which they render eternal—who
talks about expressionism or the avant-garde today? Sometimes, they combine
strict reproach against institutions with the Hegelian view that "the work
of art will become an eternal transmitter of ideas and will exist so as to
proclaim, concretely and clearly, the existence of the Universal Spirit… and
that the spiritual soars over the mundane" (V; Rafailidis 1995:256). And
some other times they isolate the artistic film as a work which, in itself,
refers exclusively to the "textual" interaction of its codes (ib.
1995:249); namely, it refers to the process which transforms it either in
symbolic capital for the few, or in a means of deception. This exact view of
the elite is also expressed by O. Elytis (1992:149): "The dangers
threatening it mostly derive from the fact that film is not addressed to
individuals but to groups of people, to ΄crowds΄ whose taste can never be on
the same level".
No matter how we are surprised by this, it becomes evident
that theoretical discourse receives pressure from the ideology of the hegemony;
therefore it must be subjected to revision. It must be acquitted from the
accusation of consent. When criticism arrives at its best, by analyzing the
film΄s multiple and hidden levels for those who "do not understand",
it raises suspicions of social discrimination. Speaking against films because
they contain a "political message", "spoon-feed ideas" to
the audience, are "grotesque" or "militant", signifies collaboration
with the hegemony by silencing any kind of political discourse. This
collaboration also includes the assessment of films based on
"absolute" art, the rejection of emotion and passion as being
melodramatic, and the debasement of documentary films as a lower form. It is
hard to accept that rendering a film exemplary, detaching it from social and
historical reality, and placing it in the realm of timeless art as a
manifestation of the Universal Idea serves anything but the ideology of the
hegemony, which needs steadfast and timeless values in order to remain
steadfast itself.
The director must certainly know the syntactic codes but, to
quote C. Metz again, a film is not defined exclusively by these codes. A film
is a social event and, as such, it is not assessed only by its structure, but
also by its appeal, assimilation, and influence, by the social context and its
effect on it. Otherwise, it becomes obsolete.
After 1970, theoretical discourse on film stood clearly
opposite to consent with the ideology of hegemony; it resisted its pressures and
came to know its problems. I shall quote some relevant texts. "The codes
of montage are ideologically oriented… every film is a vehicle of
ideology" (N. Kolovos 1988:146); "rhythms and experiences of
(censored) culture are being recorded anew on the body of film" (Th.
Rentzis 1980:24); "in order to evolve, the Big Mute Audience does not need
information; it needs to speak" (D. Leventakos 1972:47). In 1991, the
Hellenic Association of Film Critics (PEKK) published a collection of writings
on "Politics in Film", by critics A. Tyros, T. Goudelis, N. Kolovos,
S. Triantafyllou, G. Soldatos, Th. Soumas, A. Kyriakidis, V. Kechagias and D.
Charitos; in those texts, a strong comparison is made with "the doomed
glare of the Parnassians΄ fireworks, who, from the top of Mount Parnassus, saw
their theories… wane" (A. Kyriakidis 1991:24).
However, it has not been possible to unite those reactions
into a comprehensive theoretical body, able to at least confront the ideas of
the hegemony, if not replace them. As a result, criticism was restricted to
expressing itself dually. The function of criticism in itself renders such a
goal difficult to achieve. In order to formulate a fruitful theory of
criticism, the prerequisites are a broader anthropological approach which will
reveal any silencing, abstraction, or distortion of ideology and will provide a
systemic analysis of both the aesthetic experience and the social function of
the cinema phenomenon. Thus, it will be shown that:
-art is not an eternal or ecumenical phenomenon, but it
depends on social structure, and it is perceived differently or not at all by
each culture.
-film belongs to the means of non-symmetrical communication;
the contact between transmitter and receiver is broken because the receiver
cannot answer through the same channel and has to submit to silence, while the
transmitter controls ideological discourse.
-film is not just art; it has several additional functions
such as entertainment, research, advertising etc.
-culture is not homogeneous; it contains resistance,
refutations and conflicts among various social strata and competitive elites.
-therefore, art and entertainment are not strictly separate;
they are either interchangeable or conceal contrasts inherent to the system.
-ideology is produced not only in the production and syntax
of the film, but also in its distribution.
-ideology is produced by both the interweaving of codes and
the structural models (imaginary, marvelous), which correspond to models of
consent or non-consent—not to social structures.
-the communication of ideology is conducted through the
"magic of the screen"; namely, the alteration of the viewer΄s
identity through the processing of the image and the conditions in the theatre,
which coordinate the passive flux of consciousness with the flow of the film.
-this process is reinforced by the economic and political
context, and the mechanisms through which the film is commercially distributed
(star system, advertising, censorship etc); in Hollywood, critics who wrote
negatively about a film were bought off.
There is one more issue. Confrontation of ideology is also
ideology. At the same time, there is resistance against ideology which is
expressed within the same channel (deconstruction films, documentaries) or
through other channels (abolition of the cinema theatre etc). If theoretical
discourse is to be critical and perceive the social process and its
contradictions, it must not only analyse the socio-political role of the film
and the filmic spectacle in general, or the aesthetically concealed function of
ideology, which materializes in institutions; it must also analyse the
contradictions within and the resistance against this function.
Source: altcine.com
No comments:
Post a Comment